Saturday, August 9, 2014

Libertarian Ethics Simplified

“Ethics” can be defined as a universally applicable code of conduct. If an ethical system is not universally applicable, it cannot be said to be beneficial or useful as a set of moral principles, since no relative code of ethics could be shown to be superior to the next. An ethical proposition that holds that all people must eat peanut butter and jelly sandwiches every hour is not universally applicable, nor can it be shown to be any more valid than a proposal stating that everyone must eat jellybeans every hour. A relative code of conduct cannot demonstrate its validity, and crumbles as nothing more than simple arbitrary rules. Thus, any ethical standard that is not universally applicable cannot be said to be of any use or specialty, and so a rational ethic must be a universal one.

Ethics can be boiled down to a theory of ownership. A code of ethics can hold one of two positions: either human beings possess self-ownership, or they do not. If they do not, only two options remain: either human beings must own an equally distributed piece of everyone else, or human beings arbitrarily own one another depending on relativity.

Because ethics has been defined as a universally applicable code of conduct, an ethic that surrounds itself by relativity cannot be a useful or verifiable ethic. A proposal that states that Bob owns Mike cannot be proven to be more valid than that of Mike owns Bob. It is not universally applicable as it claims that a human being not only owns himself but also has 200% ownership over himself and another person, while simultaneously holding that a human being cannot own anything.

The other option holds that every individual owns a piece of every other individual. This, similarly, cannot be held to the universal standard, as each person would be required to get permission to do anything from everyone else in the world in order to be a “good” society, including using one’s mouth to breath and communicate said permission. The ethic necessarily self-collapses.

Another option could possibly be slipped in: that no person “owns” anything. However, this proposition also necessarily collapses, seeing as if no one owns anything, no one has the right to control anything, including one’s self to communicate said ideas. Like the other propositions, this cannot stand as an ethical structure.

The only remaining option is that of self-ownership. A rational code of ethics necessarily holds that each person owns him or herself, dismissing the ethical possibility of slavery. Furthermore, the theory implicates that claiming ownership of another person is unethical, ruling out the possibility of murder, rape, or physical assault as being “good.”

Because people own themselves, it logically follows that they own their actions, and the effects of said actions. The same process as before could be applied to prove the proposal, by demonstrating that the alternatives, which must either incline that (1) everyone owns a piece of everyone else’s actions and effects, or (2) people arbitrarily own one another’s actions and effects, necessarily fail as rational ethics. This leaves the only logical conclusion being that people own their actions and the effects of said actions.

This leads to two basic conclusions: people must be responsible for violating the ownership of one another, and people own resources that they have created.

If Bob kills Mike, Bob has violated all of Mike’s ownership, and is therefore responsible for said murder (unless Mike was trying to kill Bob to begin with; in which case, Bob would be exercising whatever necessary in order to secure his self-ownership). However, if the ethical standard cannot be applied to one party, it cannot be applied to the other. If Mike were a worm, he would have no capacity to be responsible for anything; thus, Bob cannot logically be responsible for the “murder” of killing Mike if Mike cannot be responsible for killing Bob. The principle of universality concludes that the responsibility of depriving one’s ownership is one that applies to the human species, but not to incompetent species.

The second conclusion drawn from the ownership of one’s actions and effects is the ownership of property. Because using natural resources is necessary for survival, an ethical standard must hold that people have a right to use said resources, and in a universally applicable way. Since everyone owning an equal piece of everything would require the permission to use any resources from everyone else in the world, including the air required to breath in order to communicate said permission, an ethic which proposes such cannot logically stand. Similarly, an ethical standard that holds that certain people hold arbitrary claims to certain resources cannot be verified as a valid ethic. The result is the same as the extension of self-ownership: that people own the effects of their actions, including that of natural resources. For example, if one creates a fishing rod out of an untouched tree branch, it can be said that he/she owns the fishing rod.

Because people own their property, it logically follows that they can choose to transfer said ownership to that of another person if they so please. If they desire to transfer ownership conditionally, this can easily be arranged, establishing the legitimacy of trade. However, if one were to simply take the property of another, this could not stand as an ethical action, for this person’s claim to the property is no more valid than the next guy’s, destroying the entire purpose of ethics. Thus, while trade is ethical and beneficial, theft cannot be ethically upheld.

Neatly, this ownership theory falls into the “screaming chimp” ethic: that murder, slavery, rape, physical assault, and theft are “wrongs.” These traits are so well ingrained in human nature that they do not reside in the analytical part of the brain but the instinctual. People have a basic understanding that pushing a fat man to stop a train is a deprivation of his ownership rights.

Unfortunately, such ethical principles fall under Kohlberg’s post-conventional stage of moral development, which many people do not practice. Instead, people often typically carry out the conventional stage of moral development, which is to follow whatever the authority dictates. As demonstrated in the Milgram Experiment, half of participants were willing to murder a person from electric shocks because they were told to do so by a seemingly legitimate authority (Brown).

Ethical codes of conduct can be useful to guide people’s behavior, but such ethical principles must be taught and practiced in order to be of practical use. Too often, ethical principles are thrown out in the name of authority or other arbitrary criteria. In order to achieve an ethical society, we must not forget our moral and instinctual principles. As time has gone by, society has become increasingly ethical, and I can only hope that such a trend will continue.

Brown, Derren. "Milgram Experiment." YouTube. YouTube, 15 July 2007. Web. 6. Jul. 2014. .